The Social Contract According to Hobbes, Hume & Locke

Posted on February 20, 2025 by Rodrigo Ricardo

Foundations and Critiques of Modern Political Philosophy

Political philosophy has long been enriched by the idea of a “social contract” as the basis for legitimate political authority and the organization of society. In exploring this idea, three influential thinkers—Thomas Hobbes, David Hume, and John Locke—have provided distinct and sometimes conflicting perspectives that have helped shape modern understandings of government, individual rights, and social order. While Hobbes and Locke are often cited as the principal architects of the social contract theory, Hume’s skeptical appraisal of the very notion adds another layer of nuance to the debate. This article examines the social contract as articulated by these three philosophers, elucidating their arguments, comparing their perspectives, and considering the lasting influence of their ideas on contemporary political thought.


I. The Foundations of the Social Contract

At its core, the social contract is the hypothetical or actual agreement among individuals to form a society and establish a government. It is not necessarily an explicit contract signed by historical actors but rather a conceptual framework for understanding how and why political authority can be justified. The idea asserts that by coming together and ceding certain freedoms, individuals create a collective body politic that is better equipped to provide security, order, and the conditions necessary for flourishing. Both Thomas Hobbes and John Locke used this framework to explain the legitimacy of state power, but they diverged sharply on their interpretations of human nature and the implications for political authority. David Hume, although not a social contract theorist in the strict sense, critiqued the very assumptions underlying the contract metaphor, arguing that history and custom—not abstract contracts—ground political obligation.


II. Hobbes: The Absolutist Perspective

Thomas Hobbes, writing in the mid-17th century, offers one of the most starkly pessimistic visions of human nature and the state of nature. In his seminal work Leviathan, Hobbes contends that without a powerful sovereign, life in a state of nature would be “solitary, poor, nasty, brutish, and short.” According to Hobbes, humans are driven by self-interest, fear, and the desire for self-preservation. In the absence of political order, the natural condition would be a perpetual state of war of “every man against every man.”

Hobbes argues that in order to escape this chaos, individuals collectively agree to surrender their natural rights to an absolute sovereign—a person or assembly endowed with the authority to impose order and enforce laws. This transfer of power is not a literal contract written on paper; rather, it is a theoretical construct that explains why people accept the authority of a ruler even though it means sacrificing some individual freedoms. For Hobbes, the social contract is primarily about survival. The sovereign’s power, while almost unlimited, is justified only by the promise of security and stability. Once the contract is made, the subjects are bound to obey the sovereign unconditionally because the alternative is a return to the state of nature, where life is marked by constant fear and violence.

Hobbes’ theory is rooted in a mechanistic view of human behavior. The individual, driven by rational self-interest, recognizes that cooperation under a strong, centralized authority is the only viable means to achieve personal safety. In this light, the social contract is not a moral agreement based on the inherent dignity or rights of individuals; instead, it is a pragmatic solution to a dire existential problem. While his conception of the contract justifies absolute rule, Hobbes also implicitly warns that without such power, society would crumble into anarchy.


III. Locke: The Defender of Natural Rights

In contrast to Hobbes’s grim outlook, John Locke provides a more optimistic and individual-centered version of the social contract. Locke’s ideas, most fully developed in his Second Treatise of Government, rest on the belief that individuals possess certain inalienable rights—life, liberty, and property—from birth. For Locke, the state of nature is not a condition of unending war but a state of relative peace and equality in which natural law governs behavior. Yet even in this state, conflicts can arise, particularly regarding property and the interpretation of natural law, which leads people to establish governments.

Locke contends that governments are formed through a social contract in which individuals consent to delegate some of their rights to a governing authority. However, unlike Hobbes’s all-encompassing sovereign, Locke’s government is inherently limited. Its legitimacy derives from the consent of the governed, and its primary function is to protect natural rights. If a government fails in this duty or becomes tyrannical, Locke maintains that citizens have not only the right but also the duty to rebel and institute a new government. This radical idea—that political authority is conditional and revocable—lays the groundwork for later democratic theories and constitutional government.

For Locke, the social contract is fundamentally an agreement among equals. People enter into the contract not out of fear of a chaotic state of nature but because they recognize the benefits of cooperative living under the rule of law. In his view, the moral foundation of society rests on the respect for individual rights and the rule of law rather than on the coercive power of a sovereign. This more balanced account of political obligation emphasizes that government exists to serve the people rather than to dominate them. Locke’s ideas have been profoundly influential in the development of liberal democracy, inspiring revolutions and constitutional reforms around the world.


IV. Hume: A Critique of the Contract Tradition

David Hume, though often grouped with the social contract theorists, offers a fundamentally different perspective. In his works on political philosophy and human nature, Hume casts doubt on the idea that governments are formed by an explicit contract or that such a contract can serve as the basis of political legitimacy. Hume argues that political institutions are not the result of a deliberate agreement among free individuals but rather emerge gradually from long-standing customs, traditions, and historical circumstances.

Hume’s skepticism centers on the historical inaccuracy and practicality of the social contract as a literal account of political origins. He points out that no society has ever been observed to originate from an explicit, conscious agreement among individuals. Instead, government and social order develop organically over time as people form habits and establish norms. For Hume, the idea of a social contract is a useful fiction—a rhetorical device that helps to justify existing institutions rather than a historical fact. Political obligation, therefore, is not derived from an abstract contract but from the natural sentiments of loyalty, habit, and mutual advantage that bind society together.

Moreover, Hume questions the assumption that all individuals in a state of nature would be rational and capable of entering into a contract on equal terms. He highlights the diversity of human circumstances and the role of historical contingencies in shaping political arrangements. In this sense, Hume’s critique is not merely a rejection of a specific theory but an invitation to reconsider the empirical realities of political life. By emphasizing the evolutionary nature of government, Hume shifts the focus from abstract principles to the concrete ways in which institutions are sustained by common practices and shared beliefs.


V. Comparative Analysis: Divergent Views on Human Nature and Political Obligation

The social contract theories of Hobbes, Locke, and Hume reveal profound differences in their assumptions about human nature, the origins of political authority, and the purpose of government. These differences not only illuminate the debates of their time but continue to resonate in modern political discourse.

A. Human Nature and the State of Nature

For Hobbes, human beings in their natural state are driven by self-interest and fear, leading to a life defined by perpetual conflict. This pessimistic view necessitates a strong, centralized authority capable of maintaining order and preventing the descent into anarchy. Locke, on the other hand, envisions a state of nature characterized by relative peace and reasonableness. Although he acknowledges that disputes may occur, Locke believes that individuals can cooperate and abide by natural law, making the social contract a means to enhance preexisting rights rather than a remedy for savagery.

Hume challenges both perspectives by rejecting the notion that the state of nature ever existed in a form that would allow for a clear-cut contract. Instead, he argues that the origins of government are rooted in historical evolution and the gradual emergence of social customs. This empirical approach undercuts the more idealized visions of Hobbes and Locke by emphasizing the practical realities of human behavior and societal development.

B. The Role and Scope of Government

The contrast between Hobbes and Locke is most evident in their visions of the sovereign. Hobbes supports an almost absolute sovereign whose primary role is to impose order and prevent the chaos of the state of nature. His ideal government is one that wields unchecked power to secure the collective safety of its subjects, even if this means limiting individual freedoms drastically.

Locke’s conception of government is markedly different. For Locke, the state is a fiduciary institution established to protect natural rights. His social contract implies that government power is limited and conditional, bound by the need to respect the inherent rights of citizens. When a government fails in this duty, Locke argues that rebellion is not only justified but necessary. This view has had a lasting impact on democratic and constitutional theory, promoting the idea that political authority must always be accountable to the people.

C. Legitimacy and the Nature of Political Obligation

Hobbes and Locke both derive political legitimacy from the consent of the governed, but the nature of that consent diverges sharply. In Hobbes’s framework, the consent is primarily driven by the desire for security and the avoidance of violent chaos. It is a contract of necessity, one in which the individual sacrifices certain freedoms for the sake of collective survival. Locke’s model, however, posits that political obligation arises from a rational recognition of mutual benefits. Citizens consent to government not solely out of fear, but because they see the value in a system that protects their rights and facilitates cooperation.

Hume’s intervention in this debate is to question the very foundation of the consent paradigm. He argues that the consent imagined by Hobbes and Locke is more theoretical than real. In Hume’s view, political allegiance is less a matter of formal contract and more a result of longstanding practices, habitual obedience, and the gradual accumulation of institutional legitimacy. This perspective challenges the idea that a single moment of conscious agreement can explain the complex web of relationships that underpin modern states.


VI. Modern Implications of the Social Contract Debate

The debates initiated by Hobbes, Locke, and Hume continue to influence contemporary political thought. Their ideas form the bedrock of discussions about the role of the state, the nature of individual rights, and the legitimacy of political power.

A. Authority and Governance

In today’s political landscape, discussions about the proper balance between state authority and individual freedom often reflect the tensions identified by these philosophers. The Hobbesian view finds echoes in arguments for strong governmental measures in times of crisis—whether in debates about national security or public health emergencies—where the need for order may require temporary restrictions on personal liberties. Conversely, Locke’s insistence on natural rights and limited government resonates with liberal democratic ideals, inspiring movements that challenge governmental overreach and demand accountability.

B. The Evolution of Political Institutions

Hume’s historical and empirical approach remains particularly relevant in an era when the origins and evolution of political institutions are increasingly scrutinized. His emphasis on custom, tradition, and the gradual development of norms provides a framework for understanding how societies adapt to changing circumstances without resorting to radical theoretical reconstructions. Modern political scientists and historians often view institutions as emergent phenomena rather than the product of deliberate design, echoing Hume’s skepticism about the literal existence of a social contract.

C. Rights, Responsibilities, and the Rule of Law

The legacy of Locke’s thought is perhaps most visible in modern constitutional democracies, where the protection of individual rights is enshrined in law and governmental power is subject to checks and balances. His theory has underpinned arguments for civil liberties, judicial review, and the idea that governments are servants of the people rather than masters over them. The social contract, in Locke’s formulation, remains a powerful justification for revolution and reform when governments fail to uphold the trust placed in them by citizens.

D. Critiques and Reinterpretations

Critics of social contract theory—drawing inspiration from Hume’s skeptical approach—argue that relying on an imagined historical contract can obscure the real, messy processes by which political communities form. Instead of a clear, definitive agreement among rational individuals, the evolution of government is seen as a complex interplay of culture, economic factors, and power relations. This critique has given rise to alternative approaches in political theory that emphasize social practice, historical context, and the importance of institutions in shaping political behavior.


VII. Concluding Reflections

The social contract as conceived by Hobbes, Locke, and critiqued by Hume provides a rich tapestry of ideas that continue to challenge and inform our understanding of political legitimacy. Hobbes’s view underscores the necessity of strong, centralized authority to prevent chaos in a world where human nature is inherently self-interested and conflictual. Locke’s more optimistic and rights-based theory, in contrast, elevates the importance of individual liberty and the conditional nature of governmental power, arguing that political authority is valid only so long as it protects the fundamental rights of its citizens. Meanwhile, Hume’s critique invites us to look beyond abstract theories and to appreciate the historical, habitual, and evolutionary dimensions of political life.

These competing visions are not merely academic; they resonate in everyday political debates about the limits of state power, the rights of the individual, and the legitimacy of government actions. When governments enact policies that impinge on civil liberties in the name of security, one can see the shadow of Hobbes’s logic at work. Conversely, when citizens mobilize to defend their rights and call for governmental accountability, Locke’s ideals come to the fore. And in both cases, Hume’s reminder that political institutions are the result of long, often unremarkable, historical processes encourages a cautious approach to theoretical abstractions.

Ultimately, the enduring relevance of the social contract debate lies in its ability to frame the perpetual tension between order and liberty. It challenges each generation to consider the balance between collective security and individual freedom, to reflect on the origins of political authority, and to ask whether the institutions that govern us are truly responsive to the needs of the people. As modern societies grapple with new challenges—globalization, technological change, and evolving social norms—the ideas of Hobbes, Locke, and Hume continue to offer valuable insights. They remind us that while the specifics of government may change, the fundamental questions about human nature, justice, and political obligation remain as urgent as ever.

In sum, the social contract theories of Hobbes, Locke, and Hume represent distinct responses to the perennial problem of political order. Hobbes’s emphasis on the necessity of a strong sovereign contrasts with Locke’s vision of a government that exists to protect inherent rights, while Hume’s historical skepticism serves as a counterweight to overly simplistic or idealized accounts of political origin. Their ideas together provide a framework for understanding not only how societies have been organized in the past but also how they might be reimagined in the future. As contemporary political challenges continue to evolve, these foundational debates offer a timeless reminder that the legitimacy of power rests not on abstract theories alone, but on the lived experiences, traditions, and rights of those it governs.


This exploration of the social contract according to Hobbes, Hume, and Locke demonstrates the depth and complexity of their ideas. While their conclusions may differ, each thinker compels us to question the nature of political obligation and the justifications for authority, thereby ensuring that the debate remains vibrant and relevant in modern discourse.

Author

Rodrigo Ricardo

A writer passionate about sharing knowledge and helping others learn something new every day.

No hashtags